1. Scope
and objectives of the report
1. While the economic crisis in Europe remains a central
concern in the nation States, the way the integration of Europe
happened and particularly the form and polity of the European Union
has become a matter of reflection, criticism and political disputes.
At the same time as the management of the euro crisis has led to
a Europeanisation of fiscal policies, citizens have lost trust in
the European Union and its institutions. Many have blamed European
integration for negative economic consequences or social disparities
affecting nation States in different ways and to varying extents.
2. European integration, leading to “an ever closer union”, is
no longer accepted as a guideline for the future and for institutional
policy. This permissive consent already began to erode during the
last decade of the 20th century. Scholars have put the possibility
of disintegration on their research agenda.
The
rise of nationalist parties indicates that politics in Europe is
no longer about State versus market or a liberal versus a social
Europe, but about European integration versus re-nationalisation
of governance.
3. In consequence, a new debate is currently taking place concerning
the political order of Europe, which goes far beyond particular
matters of Treaty amendments of the European Union. It relates to
a broader spectrum of alternatives between a European State and
dissolution of the European Union. The (at least partial) re-nationalisation
and re-regionalisation of policies has meanwhile been recommended
even by pro-European scholars as a way of reducing disintegrative
pressure
.
4. This basic question and its politicisation are not a problem
per se. Yet it may become a serious problem if the debate turns
into a confrontation of parties defending extreme alternatives without
clearly showing the consequences for the relation between economy
and politics, the relation between the power of the markets and
the power of the people, as well as for the future of democracy.
The result may be a blockade, fragmentation or degeneration of European
governance, with negative effects on democratic legitimacy.
5. In order to avoid such a confrontation, the debate needs to
be channelled into legitimised and appropriate fora and needs to
be directed from ideologies to the real challenges to be addressed.
Beyond the management of the fiscal and economic crisis, the main
challenge the European Union is currently facing is the need to
advance in the process of democratisation and correct the power
shift from the nation State to transnational markets, from national
political institutions to transnational economic forces. Or as Ulrich
Beck, Professor in London and Munich, put it recently: “My vision
for Europe does not want to overcome the States; in our age of cosmopolitism
they have to be empowered again and capable to act. The conditions
for this are democratically legitimate institutions, which reach
farer then the nation State.”
6. For his part, the former Prime Minister of Italy, Enrico Letta,
when presenting his government a year ago, on 29 April 2013, underscored
the legitimacy crisis the European Union was facing and concluded:
“The port towards which we are heading is called the United States
of Europe and our ship is democracy. We should not dream the dream
of others, we have ours, and this is the dream of European political
unity.” Two days later, in Paris, on 1 May 2013, Enrico Letta firmly
pronounced himself in favour of a “federal Europe”, considering
that the European continent could not be united only through its
currency, not even only through its historical past; the states
of the European Union should rather share a “common destiny”. “If
we are not capable of looking far towards the future, all together,
we will not make it”, he added.
7. More recently, Romano Prodi, also former Prime Minister of
Italy and former President of the European Commission, called for
a “federal Europe”, rather than “a Europe of nations”, as the remedy
to the errors of the past.
8. Italian politicians can be so engaged for a European Federal
constitution because Italy is the only European country where the
majority of the citizens decided that they want them to do so. On
18 June 1989, 88% of the 81% Italian citizens who participated in
the referendum decided that the European Parliament should get the
mandate to establish a European federal constitution. This referendum
was based on a proposition of the
Movimento
Federalista Europeo, an organisation founded in 1943
by a group of antifascists around Altiero Spinelli (see also paragraph
12 below). The proposition was signed in three months in 1988/1989
by 114 000 Italian citizens. The basic idea behind Spinelli’s organisation
and its successful referendum was the following: “A real European
transnational Democracy can never be the result of an intergovernmental conference
or a treaty but can only be established by a constitution making
process and its result, a European constitution, accepted by the
majority of the European citizens and the member States in a European Referendum.”
9. After 20 years in the European Parliament, the Green politician
Daniel Cohn-Bendit, one of the few MEPs elected in two different
countries, shares a striking conclusion in one of his most recent
interviews: “The way Germany is dominating politics in Europe is
in contradiction to the founding idea of Europe: never again should
a country play a hegemonic role. But this is today the reality,
Germany dominates everything. … Europe was never as much needed
as today. But we are much too less courageous in the way we integrate
Europe. Today the Germans seem to be the winners; but they forget
that, in the future of our globalised world, no European State,
including Germany, will be strong enough to belong to the eight
biggest industrial powers of the world. This is so because European
integration is much too slow. Our sovereignty will be, in the future,
a shared European sovereignty and no longer a pure national one.”
10. In my opinion, the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of
Europe constitutes today an ideal forum for the debate on the future
political order of the European Union and more specifically the
challenges of a federal Europe. As it bridges the emerging divide
between European and national arenas of politics, it can discuss without
being immediately involved in day-to-day politics or being pressed
by the need to make decisions. Its clear added value is that it
is composed of representatives of national parliaments who can enrich
and enlarge the debate back home.
11. But this is not the only reason for which the theme on the
challenges of a federal Europe could and should be discussed by
our Parliamentary Assembly, despite the fact that it does not seem
to directly concern all 47 member States in a similar way. To start
with, the legitimacy of our debate flows from the very initial project.
What many of the Council of Europe’s founding fathers had in mind
in the mid 1940s, after the Second World War, when they imagined
how the European community was to be constructed in order to prevent
a third world war, and how to guarantee the well-being of all Europeans
and to achieve better democracy on the continent, was precisely
a federal Europe. They then imagined a European community based
on a European constitution, which would be accepted in a European
referendum by a majority of the citizens and the future member States.
The member States would transfer to the community a part of their
sovereignty in order to promote common economic, social and security
policies under the control of a bicameral European Parliament.
12. One of those Europeans who elaborated a vision of a European
federation was the Italian Altiero Spinelli (1907-1987). In “the
Ventotene Manifesto”, Altiero Spinelli, together with his fellow
prisoner Ernesto Rossi, wrote during their imprisonment on the Italian
island of Ventotene in 1941: “The general spirit today is already far
more disposed than it was in the past towards a federal reorganisation
of Europe. The hard experience of the last decades has opened the
eyes even of those who refused to see, and has matured many circumstances favourable
to our ideal. …[T]he foundation must be built now for a movement
that knows how to mobilise all forces for the birth of the new organism
which will be the grandest creation, and the newest, that has occurred in
Europe for centuries; and the constitution of a steady federal State,
that will have … the means to see that its deliberations for the
maintenance of common order are executed in the single federal State,
while each [member] State will retain the autonomy it needs for
a plastic articulation and development of a political life according
to the particular characteristics of the various people.”
13. The German philosopher Hannah Arendt, who had to search for
refuge first in Paris and later in the United States during the
Second World War, might have captured the mood of intellectuals
as well as of many Europeans when she noted in 1945: “A real peace
we will only achieve when nation States are ready to transfer a
part of their economic and political sovereignty to a higher, pan-European
authority. What kind of Union this will be, a European Council,
a federation or the United States of Europe, is of secondary importance.”
14. In spring 1948, 190 MPs of the British Parliament and 169
MPs of the French National Assembly called for “the establishment
of a European constitution providing for an Assembly with the duty
to set up the institutions of a democratic European federation.
This Assembly should be constituted by delegates from the parliaments
of all European nations which were ready to unite themselves in
a European federation”.
15. The stage was therefore set for the creation of the Parliamentary
Assembly of the Council of Europe, which was created a year later
in May 1949. But the original motivation of the most engaged pioneers
failed. The Assembly was not empowered as the constitution-making
body of a European federation. This was the reason why its first
president, Paul-Henri Spaak (1899-1972), resigned from the presidency
in December 1951, protesting against the fact “that it was no longer
this Assembly which was fighting for a United Europe”.
16. This ambition to create the constitution-making Assembly for
a European federation was too high for those times; the necessary
conditions had not yet been achieved. The original goal and federal
project were thus later abandoned in favour of a more pragmatic
concept. Instead of a constitution, a treaty would be the basis;
instead of citizens, the governments would be the driving forces,
and, instead of politics, the starting point would be common economic
efforts.
17. This second-best economical, governmental and treaty-based
“elitist” way was so successful that in the early 1990s, when the
historical conditions for a come-back to the original federal model
of the European integration could have been met, it was simply forgotten
by most of the leading actors. They went even further in the second-best
way of integration; a common currency was decided without a real
common European democracy to legitimise common fiscal, social and
economic policies.
18. It is clear that when the European Union undergoes a profound
institutional crisis, as is the case today, all Council of Europe
member States, linked to the European Union in different ways and
to different degrees, suffer from the consequences of the crisis.
They thus have also an interest in the realisation of institutional reforms
which could save the Union, as well as the euro, but could bring
the citizens, their needs and their interests back into European
politics.
19. Moreover, reflections on the developed federal model for the
European Union can inspire individual Council of Europe member States,
as well as their MPs and citizens, whether or not members of the
European Union, in the designing of their own political organisation.
Last but not least, I would argue that if there are two unions currently
in the making in the larger Europe, that of the Council of Europe,
namely the European Union and the Eurasia, they both have to reflect
on how to organise the relation between political integration, on
the one hand, and economic integration, on the other. In this respect,
all Council of Europe member States are concerned by the discussion.
20. We are not the only ones who think the moment has come for
Europeans to be asking the question of federalism. The very experienced,
long-serving British MEP, Andrew Duff, wrote recently: “If the European Union
wants to save the Euro and wants to prevent Europe from drifting
apart, then it has to face the federal basic question, how a better
and deeper integrated European Union should be governed.” Duff reminds
us that the European Parliament might call for a new Convention
to discuss this question and he thinks this should happen shortly
after the British elections in May 2015.
21. For all the above reasons, this report, based on research
done by Professor Arthur Benz, from the Darmstadt University of
Technology, intends to contribute to this discussion by elaborating
the idea of a federal democracy for Europe in order to re-empower
democracy, renew European integration polities and overcome the
different crises and alienations today’s Union suffers from, thus
distancing itself from millions of Europeans who would like to see
the European Union as part of the solution and not part of the problem.
The report follows previous work done by the rapporteur on the problems
of democracy in contemporary Europe in reports on: The state of
human rights and democracy in Europe (
Resolution 1547 (2007)); The state of democracy in Europe – Specific challenges
facing European democracies: the case of diversity and migration
(
Resolution 1617 (2008)); Democracy in Europe: crisis and perspectives (
Resolution 1746 (2010)); and The crisis of democracy and the role of the State
in today’s Europe (
Resolution
1888 (2012)).
22. For a long time, federalism has been used as a concept for
integrating nation States, in Europe and elsewhere (India, North
America and South Africa). Yet this concept has caused many misunderstandings which
still burden our discussions and have to be overcome. For instance,
federalism has, wrongly, often been seen and understood as an obstacle
for democracy. The present report explains that the idea of a federation is
founded on a particular understanding of both the concept of federalism
and the concept of democracy and gives reasons why a federal Europe
could be more effective, democratic and stable and also better serve
the citizens than a Europe of (co-operating or competing) nation
States or a European State.
2. The concept of
federalism
23. Federalism relates to a principle of organising a
polity by dividing powers between orders of government. Rather than
constituting a model or an ideal for an ever closer political union
or a European State, it points out a process of balancing power
in a differentiated political order.
For this reason, it can provide a useful
frame of reference guiding the necessary political discussion on
alternative ways to effectively and convincingly govern Europe.
24. The concept of federalism has different historical roots.
This explains diverging interpretations
of the concept, which leads to some confusion in discussions. In
continental Europe, the idea of federalism emerged in the 16th century
as an alternative to the notion of a sovereign power. Johannes Althusius
(1604)
formulated
the most prominent version of this federal theory, by which he challenged
Jean Bodin’s argument for a sovereign State.
25. This political idea, founded on the political theology of
Reformed Protestantism, re-emerged in the late 18th century in the
newly created North American States. The founders of the United
States Constitution transformed this idea in order to justify the
unification of independent States co-operating in a confederation. In
order to distinguish the newly created sovereign union, the founders
invented the term federal government.
For
this reason, the Anglo-Saxon use of federalism usually refers to
a compound, but sovereign State and a process of centralisation
(or integration), while the same term points to a decentralised
system in the continental European tradition, where the principle
of subsidiarity is part of the concept of federalism.
26. Subsidiarity relates to responsibility and the distribution
of powers within a federal system and signifies that responsibility
is to be given in principle to smaller units. The original justification
for such priority in the Protestant Reformed church and in Catholic
social teaching was the premise that the natural community (family,
community) should not be restricted through State control.
27. The contemporary justification refers to proximity to citizens
and opportunities for participation, i.e. to democracy. As a rule,
however, these reasons are not reflected, and the old understanding
of a basis in the community still resonates. Thus the concept is
not completely problem-free.
28. Subsidiarity emphasises variety, whereas federalism demands
a balance between unity and variety. In other words, federalism
should be regarded as a precondition for the application of subsidiarity,
and in that respect, the two concepts should be interlinked.
29. Thus subsidiarity is the guiding principle within a federation
for the distribution of powers (in the event of doubt, for devolution,
whereas any centralisation needs to be explicitly justified). It
is only the principle of federalism that justifies integration between
small units, regions or States, on condition that these are not swallowed
up by unity. In this respect, it could also be argued that federalism
and subsidiarity are concepts which mean different things, but that
they are interdependent – at least in the understanding of federalism shaped
in Europe and argued for by the rapporteur.
30. Meanwhile, comparative research on federalism has discovered
a range of different varieties of federal systems, including confederations,
dual (interstate) federal governments, co-operative (intrastate)
federal governments, mono-national or multi-national federal States,
centralised and decentralised federations, etc.
This diversity indicates
that federalism never exists as a static structure but evolves and
remains, for the most part, as a process.
31. Given the interdependence and diversity of economies and societies,
neither the sovereign nation State nor a “supra-national” European
State offer feasible alternatives for a good political order of
Europe. From a pragmatic point of view, other scenarios of possible
political structures need to be compared. According to a first scenario,
nation States mutually adjust their policies in an “anarchic field”
.
In a common market, their governments have to respond to the dynamics
of competition in the market. A second scenario implies a multilateral
intergovernmental order where governments negotiate joint decisions
and settle treaties ratified by their democratic institutions; and
a third alternative consists of a real federal order of Europe.
Today’s European Union includes elements of all three scenarios
which produce a kind of over-centralised, under-democratised polity
which disintegrates and endangers the variety rather than integrating
the different peoples and convincing most citizens.
32. The first alternative cannot guarantee effective and democratic
governance since it is likely to end with powerful States dominating
the others and to cause serious co-ordination deficits, which would
thwart good governance in the affected States. Intergovernmental
policy making can in principle foster democracy. However, a democratic
Europe can better work in a federal order, despite all tensions
between federalism and democracy, as will be explained below. Moreover,
federalism constitutes a framework in which other alternatives of
inter-State relations can be turned into effective and democratic
modes of governance.
33. Intergovernmental and federal political order have often been
distinguished according to the degree of decentralisation versus
centralisation of power or of autonomy versus integration of constituent
units. However, this is a misleading categorisation.
34. In fact, a federal order consists of at least two levels of
government, the union and its constituent States with both having
legislative powers. These powers can be more or less centralised
and uniform, but in principle, a federal system is “non-centralised”.
It is for this reason that the federal
model, as defined in this report, can be of interest to big States,
in order to strengthen the unity in diversity, avoiding centralisation
and without endangering the autonomy of those who ask for as much
subsidiarity as possible.
35. Yet in order to become stable and integrate different communities
of people, federalism must be based on democracy. If the central
government selects and controls lower level governors or if authoritarian governments
at both levels join power against the people, a federal order turns
into an empty shell, as can be observed in Russia after 2004, or
in Latin American federations under military governments (Argentina,
Brazil). Under authoritarian rule, conflicts among territories may
be suppressed for some time but they intensify under the surface
of central rule.
36. In intergovernmental policy making, a high degree of uniformity
is possible through policy-specific agreements, which imply a concentration
of powers in negotiating governments. In a federal Europe, law is legitimised
by decision of legislative institutions of the Union, while intergovernmental
law is based on treaties concluded by national governments and ratified
by their parliaments. In the federal model, the interests of the union
are expressed by its own institutions, whereas in an intergovernmental
order, they result from negotiations among governments of the constituent
States. Federal institutions bring together representatives of the
union and the member States. Hence, while intergovernmental governance
implies a horizontal division of powers, federalism adds a vertical
dimension of division of powers.
37. Viewed in this way, a federal Europe is closer to the reality
rather than to a vision, although essential elements of a federal
Europe – constitution, bicameral system, clear separation of powers,
anti-centralisation protections – are still missing or not sufficiently
implemented. If a return to the nation State must be ruled out in
view of the interdependence of economy and society, the challenge
is to find a balance of powers between European, national and sub-national
institutions which is appropriate to the fulfilment of functions
and to the diversity of member States. Moreover, institutions and
processes of democracy must be adjusted to the multilevel character
of politics and policy making.
3. The concept of
democracy
38. Different types of democracy have been proven to
work in modern societies on the communal, regional, and national
level. They emerged during the late 18th century. In this period,
the ancient understanding of democracy as governing by many, i.e.
by all or a majority of citizens, was transformed into the idea
according to which some govern but all citizens participate in the
election of the government. Those governing act as representatives
for the people and are accountable to citizens who control the government.
In some systems, all citizens can even take part in the making of
the laws and the development of the constitution, prepared by the
representative bodies. In all cases, representatives have to be
trusted by citizens and to be held accountable.
39. Thus representative democracy was designed as a mechanism
inducing governments to make decisions that come close to the will
of the people. If political decisions deviate from the will of the
people, it compels governments to revise them accordingly. Direct
democracy always includes a representative body but does not reduce
the institutional participation of citizens to its election; in
fact it enables them also to decide on laws and constitutional amendments
by people’s votes, triggered by initiatives and referenda.
40. Representation constitutes a “vertical” relation between legitimate
institutions and citizens, with the former being responsible to
decide on and implement the presumed common good and the latter
controlling and acting in complementarity whenever decisions of
rulers seem not to be in conformity with their perception of the
common good. In a continuous process of responsive and accountable
governance, representatives and citizens can find out and put into
practice what is the best decision for all citizens. In a strong
democracy there is a government by, for and with the people and
the political power is shared horizontally and vertically between them
in a subtle way.
41. Beyond the vertical relation between representatives and the
represented, democracy requires that citizens are bound together
in a horizontal relation of communication and recognition.
If they only regard policy
proposal or decisions from an individualist point of view, they
would never accept decisions with redistributive effects, and those
in power would be inclined to avoid such decisions.
42. Therefore, democratic governance requires that citizens reflect
their own interests in the light of the interests of others, which
they recognise as equally justified. Citizens act for what they
perceive as the common good, which is more than just the sum of
private interests. These horizontal relations of trust and communicative
processes, disputes and efforts of understandings turn the many
isolated individuals into a “people”, not in the sense of a closed
community defined by shared norms and a common culture, but in the sense
of a communicating plurality of citizens.
43. In processes of public communication under the condition of
mutual recognition, citizens are also able to organise parties competing
for power, providing alternative proposals for policies and office
holders, mediating between representatives and the represented and
supporting public communication among citizens.
44. This idea of representative democracy became the core principle
for organising permanent governance in modern States and the basic
source of legitimacy. However, the reality of representative democracy
is far from perfect, both concerning the vertical and the horizontal
dimension. Therefore, this core of democratic representation is
embedded in additional structures and processes. They include decision-making
by citizens in the form of initiatives and referenda; the participation
of associations in a pluralist or corporatist pattern of interest
intermediation; diverse modes of monitoring of policy making by
media; scientific institutions, private organisations or international
organisations; institutions and procedures designed to control office
holders in systems of checks and balances. They also include decision-making
by courts and supplementary sources of legitimacy by expertise or
law. These elements may support responsiveness and accountability
of those in power to citizens, but they can never replace them.
45. Regarding Europe, it has been argued that democracy fails
for basically two reasons: on the one hand, the relations between
representatives and citizens are rather weak and characterised by
information asymmetries; on the other hand, scholars have maintained
that there exists no “demos”
(“people”) in Europe as the latter is composed of well-established
nations. The second aspect could justify a federal order bringing together
multiple “demoi” (“peoples”).
In fact, there are already old democracies where the State includes
many different nations and demoi (Belgium,
Canada, Switzerland). These multinational States and democracies might
illustrate that a demos, as
the basis and source of power in a democracy, can also be composed
by different demoi and that
this is not only possible when all the people have the same history,
language or cultural identity.
46. As can be exemplified by experience in these federations,
in a functioning multinational democracy, citizens reveal multiple
loyalties at national, regional or local levels. These loyalties
are not given but result from political practice and participation
of citizens in policy making, which may be quite different. In Switzerland, direct
democracy has contributed to bridging the linguistic and cultural
divides between parts of the country. In Belgium, decentralisation
has led to the dissolution of State-wide parties but still organisations
of social partners and their pragmatic co-operation in social policy
hold the country together. In Canada, decades of public debates
about the constitution created a common understanding among citizens
and political leaders in the provinces that the diversity of people
is more a benefit than a burden for the democratic State. Therefore we
have every reason to assume that the duality of people as a European demos and national demoi does not burden but rather
enriches democracy.
47. However, federalism is criticised for aggravating two basic
problems: on the one hand, it further dissociates power from citizens,
as powers are delegated to European institutions; on the other,
it constrains the equal recognition of citizens by giving precedence
to the representation of governments or nations. Indeed, the challenge
of a democratic federalism is to maintain an appropriate balance
of power. Moreover, in a multinational federation linking multiple demoi, the concept of representation
needs to be adjusted to the multilevel structure. Yet, a federal
order establishes conditions for enriching representative democracy
with additional elements.
4. Democratic federalism:
safeguards for a federal balance of power
48. A democratic government creates power and at the
same time limits the power of elected representatives. Federalism
further limits the power of democratic governments. Nonetheless
it has often been argued that, due to inbuilt mechanisms of centralisation,
a federal Europe risks becoming over-integrated, and many of those
pointing out this risk maintain that European integration has already
transgressed the threshold of an appropriate shift of powers from
the nation States. These arguments echo similar debates in federal States
like the United States or Germany, where centralist trends indeed
prevailed. Others have argued that a federal Europe lacks the integrative
forces holding the union together.
They
often refer to failed federations such as the former Yugoslavia
or the dissolution of the USSR. Yet in democratic federations, countervailing powers
exist against over-centralisation, whereas failed federations often
lacked democratic institutions designed to manage conflicts. Democratic
federalism establishes institutions and procedures conducive to maintaining
a balance of power.
49. In any event, a federal system needs integration mechanisms.
Discussing the differences is precisely the best way to integrate
diversity. In this sense, the Swiss direct democracy contributes
essentially to the integration of a very diverse and decentralised,
but nevertheless integrated State.
50. Indeed, federalism does not mean bringing different polities
together as one, however decentralised. It means instead retaining
what is separate, the
demoi,
in spite of all that is common. Federalism thus does not mean more
Europe and fewer nation States. Nor does it simply mean decentralised
government. Instead, it is a mode of organisation as old as human
society that is more compatible with the existence of many
demoi than that of a single
demos.
It constitutes
a political system which requires a continuous balance between integration
and differentiation.
51. From a comparative perspective, no political order which is
feasible for organising the European Union promises to avoid risks
of either too much centralisation or integration or too much differentiation
that can lead to disintegration. Indeed, the other models mentioned
above which may cope with the interdependence between nation States
are no less prone to these risks and probably more unstable than
the federal model, although the consequences of failure are different.
52. In an anarchic field of interdependent States, mutual adjustment
cannot guarantee the solution of common problems or divergences
between national jurisdictions if no hegemonic government takes
the lead. However, an imbalance of power can provoke the use of
force to settle conflicts by unilateral decision. Failure of intergovernmental
politics may end in an anarchic field of sovereign nation States,
if enduring deadlocks lead to dissolution of treaty-based governance.
53. A federal order, too, is notoriously instable
and vulnerable
to centralist trends or, in the case of unsettled conflicts, to
disintegration ending in an intergovernmental structure. Yet, in
contrast to the other two types, the balance of a federal order
can be maintained by institutional safeguards working against over-centralisation
and disintegration, whereas an intergovernmental order depends on
the commitment of the individual governments, each of them being
in a position to threaten their exit.
54. The possibility to vary the degree of centralisation and decentralisation,
which is not available in other political orders, is the main cause
as to why federal orders are instable: policy makers at the different
levels not only deal with policy issues, but also fight for power.
As a rule, it is the executive that is involved in this struggle for
power and that can profit from governance at various levels. Therefore,
instability may also cause a deficit in democracy. On the other
hand, democratising federalism contributes to stabilising the balance
between centralisation and decentralisation or unity and diversity,
provided that democracy is strengthened at the different levels.
55. The challenge of a federal Europe is to balance powers between
the different levels of governments. It is the continuous search
for balance and the existence of mechanisms correcting imbalance
which is a fundamental requirement. Therefore, federalism needs
a system of “safeguards”.
5. Lessons to be drawn
for Europe from federal experiences
56. Comparative research shows that different federal
systems provide for different institutions and combine different
procedures to counter imbalance. Some of them are based on non-democratic
sources of legitimacy, while others contribute to democratising
federal governance.
57. Most federal systems have established constitutional courts
as safeguards of a federal balance.
The German
solution, which influenced discussion on the Constitutional Treaty
in the European Union, is based on a detailed enumeration of powers
in the Constitution. Moreover, German basic law includes the principle
of subsidiarity as a legal norm. Consequently, legal proceedings
before the Federal Constitutional Court have turned out to be the
main mechanism of safeguarding a balance of power, although the
Länder governments can in principle
defend their powers by rejecting federal legislation in the
Bundesrat. While decisions on the allocation
of power are of a political nature, the German solution fosters
a juridification and de-politicisation of these decisions.
58. The European Court of Justice (ECJ) fulfils a similar function
in the European Union. In contrast to the German Court, it has contributed
to “integration by law”,
thus strengthening the power of the European
Union against member States. In Germany, court decisions can be
revised by constitutional amendments. Given the need for a unanimous
agreement of member States to change the Treaties, this is much
more difficult in the European Union.
59. In the United States, the Supreme Court plays a similarly
powerful role. In contrast to the German Federal Constitutional
Court, judges are selected, amongst other criteria, according to
their political opinions. Accordingly, their decisions are influenced
by political reasoning and this is accepted as far as constitutional decisions
are concerned. Hence, the court became part of power politics in
United States-federalism.
60. Among the political mechanisms for maintaining a balance of
power, the constitutional referendum applied in Switzerland is worth
mentioning. However, it must be noted that direct democracy there
works more or less under specific Swiss conditions (lack of a federal
constitutional court, lack of financial transparency and equity,
incomplete interface between democracy and human rights). Its shortcomings
have to be understood as a consequence of these Swiss specificities
and should not be blamed on the principles of direct democracy, which
could work much better in the interest of all citizens.
61. In the European Union, basic changes still require the unanimous
agreement of all member States, which is unlikely to be achieved
in a European referendum today. Notably, agreements of executives
preparing Treaty amendments, often initiated by specific interest
organisations, increase the centralisation of power. Therefore,
a different procedure of constitutional change in Europe would probably
produce better results towards balancing power.
62. In federal Switzerland, constitutional changes are realised
by the double majority of citizens and cantons, which in the Swiss
Federation is still seen as “the States”. This requires a solidly
constructed and nevertheless always endangered common mutual societal
loyalty that we still have to build up in the European Union. Nevertheless,
I am convinced that basic constitutional decisions can be made by
the majority of European citizens and States and that those who
would lose could accept their defeat when they have the chance to
belong to a new majority in another European constitutional referendum
in the not too distant future. As can be learned from Swiss experiences,
the probability of a successful constitutional referendum can be increased
by intense consultation with civil society organisations from different
sectors.
63. Scholars comparing federal systems agree that constitutions
and constitutional courts cannot guarantee a balance of power between
levels of government. In this respect, the mechanism of subsidiarity
control introduced by the Lisbon Treaty has recently attracted attention.
In fact,
this procedure is based on the assumption that subsidiarity is a
political principle. As a consequence, national parliaments are
responsible to see to it that the principle is taken care of.
64. The effectiveness of the mechanisms of subsidiarity control
should not be overestimated, since it requires that national parliaments
co-ordinate their interventions. So far, they only prevented one
directive proposed by the Commission from being passed by the Council
and the European Parliament. However, experiences so far are not
disappointing. Moreover, with elected institutions of the member
States checking the allocation of power, these constitutional decisions
have been democratised.
65. Another option for safeguarding a balance of power was invented
in Canada, and is also applied in other federations: it gives lower
level governments the right to “opt out” from uniform decisions.
In fact, this option empowers individual parliaments of constituent
units to counter centralist trends. In multinational federations, this
mechanism can threaten the federal balance and may provoke calls
for secession, as can be observed in Spain. Here, individual autonomous
communities can compel the central government to negotiate on a decentralisation
of powers. This constitutional provision, intended to protect the
historical autonomous communities, has stimulated competition for
power, thus threatening to weaken the central government. While political
parties at the centre were divided and unable to agree on a federal
constitutional reform, the Constitutional Court had to step in to
end this vicious cycle.
66. This experience proves that institutional devices protecting
constituent units of a federation must be supplemented by mechanisms
holding the federation together, like a constitution and constitutional
courts or, probably more effectively, veto powers of a federal parliament.
In Germany, a 2006 constitutional amendment implemented such a mechanism,
although limited to very few legislative powers. In certain areas
of concurrent legislation, the Länder can,
under qualified conditions, deviate from a federal law, as long
as the federal legislature has not revised the respective federal
law.
67. Safeguards can be more or less effective. Their effectiveness
depends on the character of the federation and the particular constitutional
problems it is confronted with. We can also distinguish safeguards
based on law and court decisions and those based on political decisions
in parliaments. The latter not only conform to the political nature
of the issue but also contribute to the democratic legitimacy of
a federal order. In the European Union, it is in particular the
mechanism of subsidiarity control which needs to be strengthened
in the “system of safeguards”.
68. Institutions and procedures stabilising the federal balance
mobilise countervailing forces against an unintended “migration”
of powers. At the same time, they compel policy makers to explain
how they intend to apply their power. In procedures determined to
define the allocation of powers, standards of policy making have to
be established. Thus, conflicts about who should get the power are
made explicit, and processes to deal with these conflicts are transformed
into deliberation on how policies are made at the different levels.
69. Accordingly, a system of safeguards in federal Europe, which
induces policy makers to justify their claims and decisions, operates
through monitoring institutions. They are of particular relevance
for democracy in transnational contexts.
Thus, while working to maintain
a balance of power between levels of government; the system of safeguards
contributes to improving accountability of government to parliaments
and citizens.
70. A federal order is threatened by instability, but the flipside
of this is the advantage of flexibility. Constitutional rules never
determine the allocation of powers in every detail. To a considerable
extent, policy makers can choose between different framings of policies.
They can be made by the union or left to lower levels of government,
and the allocation of powers of policy making often allows “self
rule” or “shared rule”. Shared rule, which would be the norm rather
than the exception in a federal Europe (like in other federal systems),
can be applied in different ways and different modes of multilevel
governance.
71. In order to co-ordinate policies across levels and between
jurisdictions, mutual adjustment of competing governments (contests
for best practices), intergovernmental negotiations of voluntary
agreements, and joint governance (based on binding agreements) can
be used as alternative modes of policy making. In any case, federalism
constitutes a variable and dynamic political system providing different
options on how to deal with tasks.
72. As mentioned above, the allocation of powers and the mode
of governance affect the way policies are made. Therefore, “constitutional”
decisions concerning the rules of policy making and policy choices
related to specific tasks are closely connected, although they have
to be distinguished from a normative point of view. This wider range
of options given in a federal order contributes to invigorating
democracy. Nevertheless, it can overload policy making with constitutional
issues. A stable federal order requires the right balance between what
is defined in a constitution and what is left to political decision
on flexible adjustment of the federal constitution. The challenge
is to determine the necessary rigidity and to open sufficient flexibility
with appropriate procedures guiding the use of such flexibility.
For
the European Union, in view of the difficulties to change the treaties
of the European Union, this is a decisive issue to address in order
to make a federal Europe work.
73. A balanced federation can be stabilised against centralisation
or disintegration by well-functioning safeguards. Apart from a constitutional
court, democratic institutions and processes constitute these provisions.
Hence only democracy can make federalism work as a political system
coping with conflicts in a multinational, plural society as it exists
in Europe.
74. By organising plurality on the principle of subsidiarity and
by dividing, and thus limiting, powers in a balanced multilevel
order, a federation establishes important conditions for democracy.
But federalism is not as such democratic. Three challenges have
to be met: 1) a European federation needs to integrate citizens
of Europe, but also citizens as members of nations; 2) it must achieve
a horizontal balance of power and opportunities among members of
the federation without undermining diversity; and 3) it must maintain effectiveness
of policy making despite the complexity of multilevel governance.
75. Democracy strengthens federal systems in two ways: on the
one hand, it creates the conditions to limit powers in a stable
way; on the other, it offers procedures which develop integrating
effects in divided societies.
76. To quote some examples, in Canada, the federal party system
has had an integrative effect. It was the development of a publicly
deliberated constitution-making process which contributed to the
integration of this very diverse society. Last but not least, one
could mention the fact that strong provincial parliamentary democracies
act significantly against a kind of federalism which would reduce
the decentralisation and lead to the mere execution of decisions
taken at a centralised level.
77. Since the 1970s, Belgium has faced six major reforms of its
federal system which has made Belgium one of the most decentralised
States. The political parties were also influenced by this decentralisation
and still exist only as regional parties. Although the federal balance
may be more precarious than the Canadian one overall, one can recognise
in Belgium factors which stabilise the federal balance, such as
the welfare State, the social partnership as well as the spirit
of consensus which marks the Belgian federal governments.
78. In Switzerland, which is still for many a multicultural or
multinational federal State although it labels itself as a “Confederation”,
direct democracy and civil society – strengthened by its participative
elements – keep the very diverse Swiss Federation together. The
direct democratic mechanisms, with the double majority of citizens and
cantons required for a federal law to be passed, which enhance legitimacy,
also contribute to the respect for the autonomies of the cantons
and the decentralised structure of the Federation.
6. Federal democracy
in a multinational Europe
79. As regards a European political union, many have
argued that democracy is bound to fail due to the absence of a European
demos, namely a community of citizens
who, with the help of the media, parties and interest groups, are
able to reflect and revise their opinion on public policies in the
light of opinions expressed by others.
In
its decision on the Lisbon Treaty, the German Federal Constitutional
Court argued that democratic legitimacy still must be based on accountability
to national parliaments rather than solely on powers exerted by
the European Parliament.
For this reason,
the court characterises the European Union as a “
Staatenverbund”, a particular association
of States combining federal and con-federal elements.
80. While it does not make the case for a return to the nation
State, the court’s reasoning on democracy can be exploited by protagonists
of re-nationalisation. However, the “non-
demos-thesis”
proves to be unconvincing, if we conceive the European Union as
a federal order which includes multiple “
demoi”.
“
Demoicracy” is defined as
a union of peoples understood both as States and as citizens.
In
fact, the European Union constitutes a dual order of democratic
representation of citizens. Associated in a European
demos by comparatively weak bonds
of a multilingual public, citizens are directly represented in the
European Parliament. The national
demoi are
represented by members of the Council who are accountable to their
national parliaments. Due to the weak ties among European citizens,
this second structure of indirect representation necessarily complements representation
in the European Parliament, while direct representation of European
citizens in the European Parliament reflects the achieved degree
of political and societal integration in Europe.
81. Representation of
demoi by
accountable executives constitutes a particular type of “council governance”.
In
the European Union, accountability binds the members of the Council
to their constituencies, but actually they are responsible to the
majorities in national parliaments. Thus the vertical structure
of representation exists. Certainly, information asymmetry to the
advantage of the executive may reduce the influence of national
parliaments, although the European Commission provides all documents.
82. However, the real problem of this indirect representation
relates to the horizontal structure. If individual parliaments pursue
pure national interests, members of the Council are either prevented
from finding an effective agreement or decide without taking into
account the opinion of their parliament, which then can only accept
or ratify. The first situation has been described as the “joint-decision
trap”,
while the second resembles a
constellation discussed in federal States as “executive federalism”.
83. Therefore, as citizens need to reflect their individual opinions
by considering the opinion of their fellow citizens, so do national
parliaments need to reflect their policy positions by considering
those of other parliaments, if the indirect representation of demoi is to contribute to defining
a common good in European governance (horizontal dimension of representation).
84. In fact, the Lisbon Treaty has introduced the concept of inter-parliamentary
relations and thus takes account of the horizontal dimension of demoicracy. Moreover, with the subsidiarity
control mechanism, it has established a procedure that can foster
these relations. In order to get their voice heard, national parliaments have
to co-ordinate their opinions, and they have started to communicate
on policy issues. Moreover, they established the Conference of Parliamentary
Committees for Union Affairs (COSAC), where members of the European
affairs committees of the national parliaments meet on a regular
basis. Conferences of special committees or exchange visits among
delegations of parliaments add to this horizontal structure of inter-parliamentary
relations.
85. So far, inter-parliamentary relations are rather fragmented
and still do not work as a relevant public forum where representatives
of multiple
demoi in Europe
communicate on policies and constitutional issues. Moreover, the
euro crisis has damaged emerging multilateral inter-parliamentary
relations and has given rise to bilateral relations.
Yet not only parliaments
of the member States are involved. If a European federation is considered
as an open polity with a variable geometry and overlapping spaces,
parliamentary assemblies of other European organisations may participate
in forming an inter-parliamentary public space. Among these assemblies,
the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe certainly has
a particular status, for historical reasons and due to its functions
and the scope of its members.
7. A federal reform
outlook for a more inclusive Europe and a stronger democracy
86. This horizontal fundament of a European federation
still needs to be further developed. However, it needs to be included
as a decisive element of a democratic federation. Therefore, instead
of searching for the ideal of a European public of citizens, a federal
Europe should be founded on a transnational public of members of
parliament representing national demoi.
This is a necessary complement to the public forum which is established
by the European Parliament.
87. Thus Europe is and will remain a continent of different nations.
If these nations are to participate in solving common problems in
European governance, they have to be included on an equal basis.
At a glance, equality of nations seems to speak for an intergovernmental
order. Yet the reality of politics in intergovernmental governance
rarely meets this requirement. Bargaining power usually differs
to a considerable extent. In contrast, a federal order allows for
correcting inequalities of nations by protecting distinct societies,
by defining minority rights and by balancing powers in the horizontal
relations between member State governments. Thus it balances equality
and diversity.
88. Diversity can justify an asymmetric allocation of powers between
levels, with the degree of centralisation or sharing of powers varying
between territories (“variable geometry”). In the theory of federalism,
overlapping functional units (like the eurozone or the Schengen
Area) are acknowledged as appropriate responses to particular interests
and capacities of member States.
They neither
contradict nor weaken the idea of a federal Europe.
89. As the euro crisis has revealed, imbalance of effective powers
among member States has its roots in economic disparities. In the
long run, a federation can be threatened by economic and social
divides, even if decision rules protect small member States or minorities.
Depending on the willingness and the capacities of the member States,
a federal Europe allows for the reduction of these economic imbalances
by various measures.
90. Neither does this mean that there should be a fiscal equalisation
at the European level in addition to the Structural Funds, nor does
a federal Europe imply a centralisation of fiscal powers. Yet given
the economic interdependence of diverse national and regional economies,
a political order of the European Union should not exclude measures
to reduce serious economic inequalities, not least since such disparities
could otherwise prove detrimental to all member States. Re-nationalisation
of Europe would thus rule out certain policy options which need
to be considered and carefully examined. Re-nationalisation, even
in a limited form, is tantamount to a refusal of solidarity.
91. In pluralist societies, political decisions cannot be justified
as “true”.
Therefore, democratic governance never
aims at
the common good, but
rather a common good considered as such by a majority of citizens
and accepted by all citizens under the provision that it can be
revised. Democratic politics needs to provide alternatives, both
regarding the holders of powers and the policies implemented. Alternatives
are generated in policy learning, which is essential for a democratic
order. This applies even more to a multinational federation.
92. In principle, a federal order increases the options for making
choices between alternative policies by dividing powers between
levels. However, powers of the different levels may be shared, and
many policies need to be co-ordinated across levels or among governments.
Thus multilevel governance gives rise to joint decision-making which
reduces choices to the lowest common denominator of interests pursued
by the different governments and usually includes the executives
and weakens accountability to parliaments. In the worst case, governance
runs into the “joint decision trap”, that is to say it allows only
incremental change of existing policies. But if political leaders
provide no alternatives, technocracy rules, elitist governance prevails, or
the pressure of constraints justifies decisions. Certainly, no political
order can rule out these patterns of power from obstructing democracy,
in particular in a crisis, but a complex multilevel order could
appear to be particularly likely to strengthen executive and reduce
choices.
93. However, provisions to empower parliaments and the existence
of arenas of multilevel parliamentary relations can precisely prevent
the rise of executive federalism or joint decision traps, as mentioned
above. Moreover, in a federal order, a limitation of choice is less
likely to occur than in political systems where power is concentrated,
since the manifold division of powers is conducive to the generation
of options. Depending on an appropriate institutional design, federalism
in particular allows for experimental policy making and policy innovation.
94. In a federal order, policy learning is supported from above
and can be induced from below. In both alternatives, the interplay
of central and decentralised governments in a non-centralised federal
order is decisive.
95. Learning from below can be stimulated by competition among
governments.
By
claiming to provide best public goods or services for their citizens,
they are motivated to trump policy proposals by opposition parties
and policies implemented by other governments. Competition between
jurisdictions can induce innovation and the diffusion of innovative
policies to other jurisdictions. As a rule, such a process of innovation and
diffusion works best in a federal order where the central government
organises the exchange of information.
96. The “Open Method of Coordination” introduced by the European
Commission was an attempt to create such a process of competitive
policy learning.
In
practice, it was undermined by the unwillingness of member States
to provide the necessary information in policy fields where the
European Union has no power to legislate.
97. Learning from above occurs if the federal government allows
experimental policy making in member States.
It
can select one State to implement a new policy in order to test
its effects, or it can induce a contest among selected governments
for best practices in a policy field. While the European Union avoids
experimental policy in the primary sense of the term, it has used
the second strategy in its implementation of the Structural Funds.
98. It is worth mentioning that federal systems may also reduce
the chances for policy learning, not only due to the need to come
to compromises among governments engaged in joint decision-making,
but also due to an economic imbalance preventing fair competition
for best practices. Policy learning requires the policy makers and
citizens to accept differences in policies made in member States,
but it also requires that all member States have an equal chance
to discover and implement innovative practices.
8. Federalism and
options for democratisation
99. As mentioned above, democracy is an ongoing effort;
it is a never ending process and can never be expected to be perfect.
For this reason, scholars point out the need for continuous democratisation
in democracies. Democratisation means to reduce the imperfections
of democracy knowing that the perfect one will never be reached.
Democratisation means the transformation and improvement of existing
democratic polities on the local, regional and national level as
much as constituting new democratic levels on the transnational
level, European as well as global.
100. A democratic federation implying checks and balances and vertical
and horizontal relations at different levels can never achieve an
optimal equilibrium. It compels actors to adjust to new constellations
and to continuously learn to find new solutions to conflicts. This
dynamic is part of the ongoing process of democratisation. Debates
about the role of parliaments or about subsidiarity and autonomy
of lower level units are indications of this process.
101. Moreover, a federal order has the advantage of opening various
access points for participation of citizens and associations, and
it allows the application of various elements adding to the basic
structure of representative democracy. The different levels of government
also constitute arenas for experimenting with different patterns
of democratisation:
- In most
democratic federations, regional and local governments provide ample
opportunities for citizen participation, citizen initiatives or
referenda, even if they play a more limited role at the central
level. In the European Union, suggestions for Europe-wide referenda
may be problematic due to the deficient public communication in
a multinational constellation, but
member States from time to time organise referenda on Treaty amendments
(compulsory in Ireland and consultative in other member States).
- Private interest groups find access at the different levels.
They are confronted with the problem of co-ordinating their opinions,
if they press for a particular policy. But a federal structure also
allows them to express diverse interests of their members, in particular
if they are divided along national lines. For governments, the division
of powers between levels creates more channels for communicating
with private interest groups, but they also are able to shield against
pressure from powerful associations by co-ordinating their positions
in joint decision-making. Federal
structures thus contribute to balance powers both between governments
and private interest groups and among organised interests.
- A federal organisation includes many organisations checking
the power of the executive. Governments at the different levels
mutually observe how other governments use their competences. Moreover,
courts play a particular role as arbiters among governments. However,
to an increasing degree, federal systems attract private organisations
evaluating and benchmarking policies of the different governments.
While this “monitoring” primarily addresses and compares lower level
governments, it takes general standards of good governance accepted
in the federation as points of references. This way, monitoring
indirectly reviews whether central policies are realistic and how
they are implemented in practice.
9. Conclusions
102. Without ignoring the indications of democratic deficits
in the existing multilevel order of Europe, there are good reasons
to argue that a European federal democracy could be more effective,
democratic and stable than a Europe of (co-operating or competing)
nation States or a European State. The idea of federalism does not necessarily
justify calls for more integration, nor does it imply more decentralisation
or re-nationalisation. It can however provide a conceptual framework
for constituting and maintaining a territorially differentiated
political system adjusted to the distinct economies and societies
of today’s European Union.
103. Federalism implies a pragmatic approach to politics. Like
democracy, it does not promise a perfect political system. Aiming
at conflicting goals, it requires continuous reflection and revision
of structures and policies. Therefore, it emphasises processes of
policy learning and constitutional flexibility in order to balance powers
and resources. Instead of opening an ideological debate, the concept
of a European federal democracy directs discussion to practical
issues. Without claiming to present a complete and detailed list
of suggestions, the practical implications and current challenges
of a European federal democracy can be summarised as follows:
- The concept of a European federal
democracy implies that integration is not a one-way street towards an
ever closer union. Therefore, the continuous search for a balance
of power between European and national institutions and modes of
multilevel governance is an essential prerequisite. This process
of balancing needs to be institutionalised in an appropriate way,
in order to enable a revision of an existing allocation of powers
and in order to check the application of powers.
- Federalism implies variety, not only between levels and
jurisdictions but also in the degree of integration of the different
territories. Policy-specific arrangements of multilevel governance
with variable territorial scope, overlapping territorial organisations
of the European space, and different kinds of partnerships with
neighbouring States characterise a federation, which is not a federal
State. This variety expresses the plurality of Europe and thus constitutes
a foundation of democracy.
- In a democratic federation, processes aimed at checking
powers and at a revision of the distribution of powers must include
parliamentary institutions at the European and national levels.
- Regarding the revision of powers, the right to initiate
change and the arenas of negotiation are not less important than
the right to decide. Accordingly, procedures for Treaty amendments
could be reconsidered. For this purpose, an inter-parliamentary
dialogue (suggested by the European Parliament as a pre-legislative
process) could give national parliaments a more effective voice
compared to current procedures. Moreover, regular evaluations of
the “state of European federal democracy”
can support the search for a federal balance, a task that probably
can be fulfilled by the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of
Europe.
- Experimental policies can increase the dynamics of power
structures in a European federal democracy. Yet they need to follow
rules, guiding and limiting the flexibility.
- Regarding checking the application of powers, the existing
“system of safeguards”, which combines judicial and political-democratic
mechanisms, could be further developed, with a particular emphasis
on the subsidiarity checks by national parliaments.
- Modes of multilevel governance in Europe should preserve
the autonomy of lower levels as far as possible. Moreover, these
modes should induce and support policy learning by allowing for
and fostering decentralised variation and comparative evaluation
of policies, within a framework of standards and procedures set
at the European level. A European federal democracy should use the
whole range of old (legislation) and new modes of governance (like
the Open Method of Coordination (OMC)) which the European Union
has developed during the last decades.
- Accountability of executives to parliaments is essential
in multilevel governance. A system of checking and revising the
balance of power by parliaments can improve accountability if the
evaluation results are submitted to public deliberation in parliaments.
- Existing horizontal inter-parliamentary relations in a
federal demoicracy could be
stabilised and extended. They are a decisive element for an effective
subsidiarity check and for effective governance.
- The differentiated structure of a federation makes it
possible to combine representative democracy with additional elements
of direct and associative (or participatory) democracy, as well
as monitoring functions. They should be used in a continuous process
of democratisation of a federal democracy, which cannot end in a
fixed institutional design but must proceed in ongoing experimental
policy making.
104. These tentative conclusions are derived from the concept of
a European federal democracy. As long as the concept of federalism
raises misunderstandings, the reasoning leading to a pragmatic approach
is not convincing. Therefore, a dialogue on what federalism means
and how it applies to Europe should aim at bridging the divergence
in definitions caused by the different historical roots of the idea.