1. Introduction
1. Assisted reproduction using
donor sperm has been in place for several decades. The European
Society of Human Reproduction and Embryology estimates that there
are more than 8 million children worldwide born as a result of assisted
reproductive technologies (ART).
In Council of Europe member States
there are different types of legislation on human gamete donation,
namely sperm and oocyte donation for treatment using ART.
2. Traditionally, most States have restricted the right of a
person born as a result of artificial insemination by donor sperm
(AID) to know their origins. This restriction may be due to legislation,
but also to the absence of a system for gathering information on
the identities of donors. In the same way as similar legal proceedings on
adoption, in cases concerning assisted procreation using human gametes
a conflict between the child’s right to information and the adult’s
right to anonymity has typically been resolved in favour of the
adult.
3. The anonymity of gamete donors was introduced in the law of
many States to ensure that donations would remain altruistic and
voluntary, and also to guarantee respect for the donor’s private
life and the interests of the legal family of the donor-conceived
person. It would seem, however, that these grounds for the principle of
donor anonymity are now, to some extent, obsolete. The principle
of the anonymity of human gamete donors is today called into question
by the increasing number of challenges thereto, by changes in society
and by the evolution of genetic technology.
4. The Committee on Social Affairs, Health and Sustainable Development
held a public hearing on the subject in Lisbon (Portugal) on 17
September 2018, with the participation of Ms Carla Maria Pinho Rodrigues (President
of the National Council of Medically Assisted Procreation of Portugal),
Mr Miguel Oliveira Da Silva (member of the Committee on Bioethics
of the Council of Europe, Portugal), two donor-conceived persons
and an anonymous donor.
5. In this report, I intend to give an overview of the international/European
legal framework and of the issues at stake. From a human rights
perspective, there is a need to find a balance between the rights
and interests of all parties concerned, i.e. donors, donor-conceived
children/persons and legal parents, clinics and service providers,
as well as the interests of society and the obligations of the State.
2. The international/European legal framework:
gradual recognition of the right to know one’s origins
6. The anonymity of human gamete
donors is no longer a principle unanimously adhered to at European level.
Internationally, a tendency towards recognition of a donor-conceived
person's right to know their origins has been emerging for a number
of decades. In 1984, Sweden was the first country to waive the principle
of the anonymity of gamete donations.
The
Swedish example was then followed by several other countries such as
Germany, Switzerland, the Netherlands, Austria, Finland, Iceland
and the United Kingdom. Recently, Portugal's Constitutional Court
held that anonymous gamete donations were unconstitutional, thereby changing
the legal situation regarding donations in Portugal and conferring
force of law on the right of access to one’s genetic origins.
There
is therefore a growing tendency to give priority to the rights of
donor-conceived persons to know their origins and to favour waiving
the anonymity of gamete donors.
7. Several international instruments reflect this development.
Firstly, Article 7.1 of the United Nations Convention on the Rights
of the Child (CRC) of 20 November 1989 provides for a child’s right
to know his or her parents ‟as far as possible”.
Article
8 of the CRC also establishes the right of the child to preserve
his or her identity, including family relations, without unlawful
interference. It goes on to provide that States shall grant appropriate
assistance and protection with a view to speedy re-establishment
of the child’s identity.
However, it
should be noted that the CRC applies solely to ‟children”.
Its
scope does not extend to adults conceived through gamete donation
who wish to know their genetic origins.
8. In the somewhat-related field of international adoption,
the widely-ratified Hague Convention on Protection of Children and
Co-operation in Respect of Intercountry Adoption posits, in its
Article 30:
(1) The competent
authorities of a Contracting State shall ensure that information
held by them concerning the child's origin, in particular information
concerning the identity of his or her parents, as well as the medical
history, is preserved.
(2) They shall ensure that the child or his or her representative
has access to such information, under appropriate guidance, in so
far as is permitted by the law of that State.”
It can certainly
be argued that the situation of donor-conceived persons is closer
to that of children who have been adopted across borders than to
recipients of organ donation.
9. The European Convention on Human Rights (ETS No. 5, “the Convention”)
may also be useful in this respect, in that it applies to all persons,
whether a minor or an adult. Since the early 2000s, the European
Court of Human Rights has given a constructive interpretation to
Article 8 of the Convention which provides for a person’s right
to respect for private life. It has, for example, held that Article
8 protects ‟the right to an identity and to personal development”,
which includes the right to access information that would make it
possible to trace ‟some of [one’s] roots”.
It has also held that Article 8 implies
the right of a person to know their origins and the circumstances
of their birth
and
a right to have access to certainty of paternal filiation.
10. The Court thus places emphasis on the vital interest of the
child, even as an adult, to obtain information essential to discovering
the truth about an important aspect of their personal life, which
includes the identity of their genitor. However, as reflected in
the Court’s judgments, the right to know one’s origins is not absolute
and must always be balanced against the interests of the other parties
concerned. What is striking is that this balancing often tends to
favour the genitor’s right to privacy, and therefore, donor anonymity.
In
addition, none of the Court’s decisions so far have specifically
concerned the right of a person conceived by means of gamete donation
to have access to information on the donor, although a number of
applications are currently pending (against France) on this subject.
It is therefore not possible
for the moment to establish with certainty whether or not the Court
is in favour of waiving donor anonymity.
11. In view of what can be perceived as the limited scope of international
instruments guaranteeing the right to know one’s origins and of
the remaining disparities between national laws, which are likely
to increase recourse to cross-border medically assisted procreation,
the Assembly should draw attention to the existing inadequacies
and make recommendations regarding the steps that might be considered
by Council of Europe member States and the Council of Europe itself
to clarify the situation and find the best balance.
3. The
issues: the various problems posed by anonymous donation of gametes
12. The anonymity of gamete donors
raises a number of issues, which lead to the question of whether
it should be maintained in the legislation of member States.
13. Firstly, the principle of anonymity of gamete donors raises
a public health issue, since it means that the donor-conceived person
cannot be informed of their genitor’s medical history. Moreover,
it increases the risk of consanguinity, as some donors who have
made several donations may end up with several children, without the
latter being able to know whether they are related when they wish
to enter into a relationship with each other.
Despite the fact that some States
limit the number of donations that can be made by a single donor, the
‟serial donors” phenomenon is exacerbated by the recurring lack
of a system for exchanging information between clinics performing
artificial insemination by donor within a State (for example, in
my home country Belgium, or, historically, in the Netherlands
), and also by the phenomenon of cross-border
donations.
14. Secondly, the principle of anonymity raises the fundamental
ethical issue of the position of the donor-conceived person. Although
the quest to find out about their identity by persons born as a
result of anonymous gamete donation differs somewhat from that of
adopted persons and may apparently seem ‟of lesser importance”,
it is nonetheless just as legitimate, as transpires from the claims
of the many associations such as Procréation
Médicalement Anonyme. Many donor-conceived persons believe
that access to their donor’s identity is a fundamental aspect of
their identity building (as children and adults), although there
are some donor-conceived persons who believe that assuring emotional
and physical security to a child is more important than transmitting
genetic material, and thus are interested only in the disclosure
of non-identifying information.
15. The principle of anonymity of gamete donors is often modelled
on the anonymous nature of organ donations, but it has different
implications. Organ donations save lives whereas gamete donations
create lives. The donation of gametes will therefore determine certain
physical characteristics of the donor-conceived person. I thus believe
that access to the donor’s identity is a fundamental aspect of the
child’s identity building. However, for a donor-conceived child
to be able to build its identity, it is, first of all, necessary
for the child to be informed that he/she was conceived of gamete
donation, which is far from being the norm, even today.
16. An American study carried out in 2017 noted that in a sample
of young American adults conceived through a sperm donation programme
with the identity of the donor being accessible, 40% asked for access
to the identity of the donor.
Another American study conducted
in 2010 showed that 65% of donor-conceived persons considered that
the donor constituted half of themselves, that 70% of them wondered
what the family of their donor was like and 69% wondered if the
donor’s family would like to get to know them.
It can therefore reasonably be assumed
that at least one out of two donor-conceived persons is seeking
to know their origins, hence the importance for these persons of
having access to certain information about their genitors. So-called “genealogical
bewilderment” and a “fractured sense of identity” can lead to considerable
suffering for donor-conceived persons who cannot access identifying
information about their donors.
It is interesting to note in this
regard that the parliamentary Victorian Law Reform Committee (Australia)
in its 2012 inquiry report recognised that “donor-conceived people
are
actually suffering from
their lack of knowledge about donors”.
17. Finally, the principle of anonymity is becoming obsolete due
to the evolution of genetic technology, making it possible for a
person to have access to their genetic data and therefore to find
their genitor. ‟Recreational” genetic tests are becoming increasingly
common worldwide and access to testing, whether via internet or
when travelling abroad, is now very easy.
Donor anonymity is,
de facto, no longer guaranteed today.
It would therefore appear more appropriate to prevent potential
excesses arising from developments in these technologies by waiving
the anonymity of gamete donors and by managing the manner in which
this information is communicated to the donor-conceived person,
instead of allowing anonymity to remain in place even though it
has now become outdated.
4. Arguments
in favour of waiving anonymity in order to better protect donor-conceived
persons
18. It should first be said that
the aim is not to abolish the anonymity requirement completely,
but simply to waive it so that the parents cannot know the identity
of the donor at the moment of insemination and vice versa, but the
donor-conceived person can later have access to certain information.
It is therefore more accurate to talk in terms of access to information
rather than abolition of the principle of the anonymity of gamete
donation. However, there would seem to be certain practical, as
well as ethical, obstacles to such a waiver of the anonymity requirement.
19. The argument systematically put forward by the clinics which
carry out artificial inseminations with donor sperm is that the
number of donors will decrease in the event of a waiver of anonymity.
However, this argument is not backed by statistics. No decrease
in donations has been noted in the countries which have granted
the right to have access to one's origins. In Sweden, for example,
the 1984 law providing for the right of donor-conceived persons
to have access to their genetic origins resulted in a decrease in
the number of donors in the first year only, but this trend has
now reversed.
In the United Kingdom, since 2005,
when the law changed, donations have steadily increased.
The different studies carried out
have shown a substantial change in the donor profile, as they are
generally older and have had time to think about their decision,
but not a reduction in their number.
20. Lastly, an ethical obstacle is often cited by those opposed
to recognition of the right of donor-conceived persons to have access
to information on their genitors: the risk of eroding the family
unit comprising the legal parents and the donor-conceived person
in favour of the donor – the biological parent – and therefore of “reducing”
filiation to biological parenthood. However, it is generally recognised
that donor-conceived persons wishing to know their genetic origins
already have parents and are not in pursuit of an emotional bond
or looking for a family, but are instead searching for a part of
their history and identity. Therefore, in view of changes in society
and in attitudes with regard to the plurality of family types which
can be noted today, it would seem easy to imagine a form of peaceful
coexistence of the truth about a person’s origins and their legal
filiation, without the latter being under threat, as they clearly
have different functions and prerogatives.
21. Furthermore, in the countries where the right of access to
one's origins has been recognised, waiving anonymity has had no
legal consequences for filiation, as it is already established between
the donor-conceived person and the legal parent.
The
donor is thus protected from any request to determine parentage or
an inheritance or parenting claim. The State and its bodies will
have an essential role to play in this development, both with a
view to eliminating the legal risks for filiation through legislation
and identifying the donors and those who receive gamete donations
in order to improve the transparency of AID techniques.
5. Balancing
all interests
22. I believe it is useful to clarify
once more who has which interests when it comes to gamete donation.
I have identified the following interested parties: the legal parent(s),
the donor(s), the donor-conceived person (as a child and as an adult),
the clinics and service providers, and society (the State).
23. The legal parent(s) are the ones who seek to found a family
with the help of ART, sperm and/or oocyte donation. Without their
wish for a child, no donor-conceived child would be born – in contrast
to adopted children or children abandoned at birth. The legal parents
have the intention, right and obligation to parent the child conceived
through gamete donation, which has led legislators and courts across
countries to ensure that their legal parental filiation is not challenged
by the donor(s). However, I am not aware of a jurisdiction which obliges
the legal parents to inform their child that he/she is donor-conceived.
Yet I doubt whether it is really in the interest of the legal parents
to preserve “family peace” by hiding the method of conception from
their child, as chances are that the child will find out at some
point in any case. “Late” or accidental disclosure may lead to a
child feeling betrayed by the legal parent(s), and may thus lead
to estrangement rather than “family peace”, which is not in the
interest of the legal parents.
However, in
some cultures (including in Europe) the use of ART continues to
be viewed negatively (though the stigma seems to be decreasing),
which can explain the reluctance of some parents to disclose.
24. What are the interests of the donor? In accordance with Council
of Europe standards, gamete donation is meant to be a “voluntary
and altruistic gesture with the sole aim of helping others”,
and
thus without any financial gain or comparable advantage for the
donor. However, this does not prevent the reimbursement of justifiable
expenses related to the donation itself (for example, travel, medication)
or compensation for loss of earnings. Some donors have admitted
having other motivations than the “sole aim of helping others”: reimbursement
of such expenses can be quite high, in particular for cross-border
oocyte donations, so sometimes there has been a financial motive;
others have given psychological reasons, such as a wish for immortality.
In most cases, it is in the interest of the donor to be protected
from legal, financial or parenting claims. However, some donors
– in particular later in life, and if they have founded no family
of their own – welcome contact with the children/adults conceived
by the donation and are interested in building a relationship with
them (which can go as far as legal filiation in isolated cases).
It is in general not in the interest of the donor for his/her identity
to be revealed without his/her consent in situations when anonymity
was promised at the time of the donation.
25. As already described above, donor-conceived children have
not just an interest, but also a right to know their parents as
far as possible; as adults, they retain the right to know their
origins and the circumstances of their birth. For medical reasons
and to avoid consanguinity, it is in their interest to have access
at least to non-identifying information about their donor(s), but
for their identity-building and personal development, having access
to identifying information is usually also in their interest.
However,
whether to exercise their possibility to access this information
should be left to the discretion of the donor-conceived persons
themselves in my view.
On another note,
I believe it is not in the interest of donor-conceived persons to
have far more half-siblings than is the norm.
26. The clinics and service-providers have an interest in being
able to offer comprehensive ART services in compliance with the
law, and an interest in keeping accurate records whatever the legal
situation in the country concerned in order to be able to comply
with that legislation (including when it is changed retrospectively). Cross-border
gamete donations and ART should be particularly meticulously documented.
27. Society – and thus the State – has an interest in ensuring
individual and public health, and thus in ensuring an adequate legal
and regulatory framework is in place which can, as a minimum, trace
donors if the medical need should arise (for a transplant, for example),
and has all the information recorded in a way that ensures that
close blood relations cannot marry. The State also has the obligation
to uphold and safeguard the fundamental rights of its citizens more
generally, including the rights of all stakeholders as mentioned
in these paragraphs, and an interest in keeping “social peace.”
28. Balancing all the above interests is not easy, and different
solutions have been found in different countries at different times.
One size may not fit all. However, it is also clear that some solutions
have been better at avoiding abuses and at keeping the “social peace”
than others. It should not be forgotten that donor-conceived persons
risk losing their lives if their donor cannot or will not be identified
(when they are in need of a transplant, for example), and that both
some donors and some donor-conceived people have suffered greatly from
accidental disclosure (including situations of consanguinity).
6. Conclusions
and recommendations
29. The distinguishing features
of the Council of Europe, namely its mandate encompassing the promotion of
human rights, democracy and the rule of law, and its role of promoting
good practice among the member States, place the Organisation in
an ideal position to address the risks and challenges related to
the anonymity of gamete donations.
It is thus for the
Council of Europe to make recommendations to States in order to improve
the protection of the rights of all the parties concerned, namely
the parents, the donors and the children, while focusing on the
rights of the donor-conceived person, who is in the most vulnerable
position and for whom the stakes appear to be higher.
30. My recommendation would thus be, for all future gamete donations
in Europe, to waive anonymity. This would mean that (except in exceptional
cases, when the donation is from a close relative or friend), the
donor’s identity would not be revealed at the time of the donation,
but upon the child’s 16th or 18th birthday,
the donor-conceived
child would be informed (ideally by the State) that there is supplementary
information available on the circumstances of his/her birth. It
would be up to the donor-conceived person whether and when to access
this information containing the identity of the donor. The legal
situation of the donor – no parental rights or responsibilities
– would not change in this scenario.
31. In this scenario, it would be up to the clinics to inform
the State upon the birth of a donor-conceived child of the child’s
and the donor’s identity, and up to the State to keep an up-to-date
register of all donor-conceived children and their donors. There
should also be an upper limit on the number of possible donations
by the same donor which would need to be properly enforced.
32. Regarding donations made in the past where anonymity was promised,
I don’t believe this should be lifted retroactively, except for
medical reasons or where the donor has consented to the lifting
of the anonymity.
No
changes to legal parentage should result from the lifting of the
anonymity even when the donor has agreed to it being lifted. Donors
should be offered counselling before they decide whether or not
to agree to lift anonymity. Proper guidance, counselling and support
should also be offered to donor-conceived persons before they decide
whether to exercise their right to access information containing
the identity of the donor.
33. These principles should be applied without prejudice to the
overriding consideration that gamete donation must remain a voluntary
and altruistic gesture with the sole aim of helping others, and
thus without any financial gain or comparable advantage for the
donor. I would suggest leaving it to the Committee of Ministers
to decide whether these recommendations should ultimately become
legally binding.